Register | Sign In


Understanding through Discussion


EvC Forum active members: 66 (9164 total)
8 online now:
Newest Member: ChatGPT
Post Volume: Total: 916,469 Year: 3,726/9,624 Month: 597/974 Week: 210/276 Day: 50/34 Hour: 1/5


Thread  Details

Email This Thread
Newer Topic | Older Topic
  
Author Topic:   Behe's Irreducible Complexity Is Refuted
DNAunion
Inactive Member


Message 104 of 223 (91465)
03-09-2004 7:12 PM
Reply to: Message 93 by Loudmouth
03-09-2004 11:53 AM


quote:
DNAunion: But by switching to gross anatomy you are demoting your counter down to an argument from analogy.
quote:
loudmouth: Behe's definition of IC does not exclude macroscopic IC systems.
Behe does exclude macroscopic biological systems — such as organs and organ systems - from being IC.
quote:
loudmouth: It is not analogy
Yes, it is.
quote:
loudmouth: Instead of dodging this IC system, why don't you confront it.
Why don’t you? Why don’t you lay out your argument that shows that the ossicles form an IC system according to Behe’s statements?
If you get all of the anti-Behe crowd here to agree on what the system under consideration actually is, and what its function actually is, then we can proceed with the analysis.
quote:
loudmouth: Show me how removing one of the parts of the middle ear will not result in the loss of sound wave transmission from the outer tympanum to the oval window of the inner ear.
I don’t need to. I’m not claiming that such would not happen. My claim is that the middle ear is not IC according to Behe, so it is irrelevant whether removing parts causes loss of function.

This message is a reply to:
 Message 93 by Loudmouth, posted 03-09-2004 11:53 AM Loudmouth has not replied

  
DNAunion
Inactive Member


Message 105 of 223 (91466)
03-09-2004 7:15 PM
Reply to: Message 103 by NosyNed
03-09-2004 7:05 PM


quote:
DNAunion: No, it doesn't refute Behe unless you can show that the system is actually IC according to Behe. Your simply stating over and over that it's IC doesn't make it IC.
quote:
NosyNed: Are you saying that if one part of the middle ear is missing it still functions?
No, I'm not saying that. I am saying that it is IRRELEVANT whether or not loss of function occurs when one of the ossicles is removed because the system is not IC according to Behe's statements.
[This message has been edited by DNAunion, 03-09-2004]

This message is a reply to:
 Message 103 by NosyNed, posted 03-09-2004 7:05 PM NosyNed has replied

Replies to this message:
 Message 106 by NosyNed, posted 03-09-2004 9:41 PM DNAunion has replied

  
DNAunion
Inactive Member


Message 107 of 223 (91489)
03-09-2004 10:48 PM
Reply to: Message 106 by NosyNed
03-09-2004 9:41 PM


quote:
No, I'm not saying that. I am saying that it is IRRELEVANT whether or not loss of function occurs when one of the ossicles is removed because the system is not IC according to Behe's statements.
quote:
NosyNed: Is this definition the Hambre gave earliy correct?
----------------------------------------------------------------------
A single system composed of several well-matched, interacting parts that contribute to the basic function of the system, wherein the removal of any one of the parts causes the system to effectively cease functioning. (Darwin's Black Box, 39)
----------------------------------------------------------------------
That definition is correct. But as with many/most concepts, a one-sentence definition doesn't say it all. After all, if that one sentence contained everything Behe wanted to say about IC, he wouldn't have written a book. In his book, Behe goes on to explain things more, such as what he does NOT means by a single system (an integrated system of systems doesn't count) as well as giving a better idea of what he means by parts.
quote:
NosyNed: How is the middle ear not IC?
Okay, looks like you guys are finally settling on the middle ear (and not the whole hearing system) as the system under consideration. Let's stick with that.
In this thread, several functions have been mentioned for the ossicles. But as I pointed out earlier, mere amplification is not what most people have mentioned. So I propose that we all accept transmission of force from the tympanic membrane to the oval window as being the function of the ossicles.
So...
SYSTEM = ossicles
FUNCTION = transmission of force from tympanic membrane to oval window
All agreed?

This message is a reply to:
 Message 106 by NosyNed, posted 03-09-2004 9:41 PM NosyNed has replied

Replies to this message:
 Message 108 by NosyNed, posted 03-10-2004 12:37 AM DNAunion has replied

  
DNAunion
Inactive Member


Message 111 of 223 (91526)
03-10-2004 8:25 AM
Reply to: Message 108 by NosyNed
03-10-2004 12:37 AM


quote:
DNAunion: In this thread, several functions have been mentioned for the ossicles. But as I pointed out earlier, mere amplification is not what most people have mentioned. So I propose that we all accept transmission of force from the tympanic membrane to the oval window as being the function of the ossicles.
So...
FUNCTION = transmission of force from tympanic membrane to oval window
All agreed?
quote:
NosyNed: No, I don't agree on "the" function. That is being a bit silly. The ossicle perform more than one necessary function. If the hearing would not work without those functions why is one of them 'the' function? Why even worry about it actually?
See, this is why people need to read Behe’s BOOK instead of just his DEFINITION!
Behe spends some time discussing MINIMAL FUNCTION. Here, that concept can help us nail down what the function of the system under consideration is. What could be lost and yet have the system still retain minimal function? Remember, Behe’s argument rests on what is REQUIRED, not on everything that is there.
If the ossicles didn’t provide any amplification for the signal, would minimal function be retained? Yes. So amplification is NOT the function of the ossicles (it’s an additional, accessory function that is not required from minimal function).
If the ossicles didn’t transmit force from the tympanic membrane to the oval window, would minimal function be retained? No. So transmission of force from the tympanic membrane to the oval window should be considered the function of the ossicles.
quote:
NoseyNed: The ossicles perform amplification, attenuation, transmission and impdedance matching. I suppose if one of them is "the" function it would be transmission. If amplification, attenuation or impdendence matching weren't working some volumes of some frequencies would still be heard. If transmission isn't working there is no hearing (or at least very, very little).
Sounds pretty good to me. Note that amplification would still exist without any contribution in amplification from the ossicles themselves due to the differences in size and mass of the tympanic membrane and the oval window.
quote:
NosyNed: But for now, for the sake of argument, ok, 'the' function is whatever you want it to be.
Sorry, not good enough. That leaves the possibility of "moving the goal post" later. Either you — plural, mind you - actually accept that the function of the ossicles is transmission of force from the tympanic membrane to the oval window (and the debate progresses) or you don’t (and the debate is at a standstill).
[This message has been edited by DNAunion, 03-10-2004]

This message is a reply to:
 Message 108 by NosyNed, posted 03-10-2004 12:37 AM NosyNed has replied

Replies to this message:
 Message 114 by NosyNed, posted 03-10-2004 10:06 AM DNAunion has not replied

  
DNAunion
Inactive Member


Message 112 of 223 (91528)
03-10-2004 8:38 AM
Reply to: Message 109 by Mammuthus
03-10-2004 4:09 AM


Re: ..or maybe actin is there after all....
quote:
However, knocking out actin makes for some pretty nasty mutants...also major or minor component is rather arbitrary. If knocking out a gene lowers fitness (even if the organism survives) it is still a major component in its pathway.
No, it's not. Lowered fitness indicates a reduction in system function, NOT loss of minimal function. If minimal function is retained, the system is still operational and the "missing part" is not a required part.
quote:
[abstract] The ida5 mutant of Chlamydomonas, first isolated as a mutant lacking a subset of axonemal inner-arm dyneins, has recently been shown to lack conventional actin owing to a serious mutation in its gene. It lacks inner-arm dyneins probably because actin is an essential subunit for their assembly.
The first sentence indicates that ONLY A SUBSET of the axonemal inner-arm dyneins is lacking: NOT ALL OF THEM. Some inner-arm dyneins were present even when actin was not. (The second sentence is less clear).
Furthermore, the following from the abstract indicates that minimal function was retained in the absence of actin since the reintroduction of actin merely increased motility (i.e., they had motility in the absence of actin, but adding actin increased it).
quote:
[abstract] "Cotransformation of the double mutant ida5arg2 with the wild-type actin gene and arginino-succinate lyase gene that suppresses the arg2 mutation yielded several transformants that displayed increased motility."
[This message has been edited by DNAunion, 03-10-2004]

This message is a reply to:
 Message 109 by Mammuthus, posted 03-10-2004 4:09 AM Mammuthus has replied

Replies to this message:
 Message 113 by Mammuthus, posted 03-10-2004 9:04 AM DNAunion has replied

  
DNAunion
Inactive Member


Message 118 of 223 (91585)
03-10-2004 1:16 PM
Reply to: Message 113 by Mammuthus
03-10-2004 9:04 AM


Re: ..or maybe actin is there after all....
quote:
If you chose to view only those mutants that completely ablate a function as critical then this is a fairly esoteric view of mutation.
You're mixing apples and oranges. When specifically discussing Behe's statements on IC then if a "part" is deleted and the result is just reduction in fitness, not loss of minimal function, then the "part" is not considered to be one of the required parts of the IC system itself.
quote:
In any case, your original point was that using textbooks you could not find references of any significant involvement of actin in cilia or flagella and this is clearly wrong.
Agreed (more or less...your statement makes it sound like it is clearly wrong that I couldn't find any references in my textbooks, which is not the case). I learned something, and already thanked you.
[This message has been edited by DNAunion, 03-10-2004]

This message is a reply to:
 Message 113 by Mammuthus, posted 03-10-2004 9:04 AM Mammuthus has not replied

  
DNAunion
Inactive Member


Message 119 of 223 (91587)
03-10-2004 1:30 PM
Reply to: Message 115 by Loudmouth
03-10-2004 11:07 AM


quote:
loudmouth: You claim that Behe excludes macroscopic IC systems. I would like a reference for this.
Sure...from my personal notes (people can skip the introduction and head straight for the quotes, if they want, without losing anything).
*****************
How many people here truly understand how a computer operates? Probably not many. I would imagine that most users know little more than what button to push to turn the computer on and what a monitor, keyboard, and mouse are (for example, many people point to the system case sitting on their desk or floor and call it a CPU!). Ask them how a CPU fetches instructions and a convincing answer will not be forthcoming. Others know computers in a bit more depth. They know that there is a thing called a hard drive that somehow holds all of their information, and that some kind of a green circuit board inside the system case houses something called the CPU (which they have no idea what it looks like) that does the thinking, etc. Understanding computers a bit better than the first group, those belonging to the second group could give a better explanation of how a computer operates. A few others know a great deal about computers. They know of the binary language and its physical representation as the presence or absence of electric charge; that a hard drive contains multiple rigid platters that spin at high rates and have read-write heads (or separate read heads and write heads) that float on a thin cushion of air just above the platters’ surfaces; and that the BIOS serves as an abstraction layer between the given hardware configuration and the operating system; etc. These people could give a very detailed and convincing explanation of how a computer operates. What we see here is that - as with most everything that science studies - the whole is understood better by learning how its parts operate. And if the parts are themselves composed of smaller parts, an even greater depth of understanding of the whole can be reached by determining how they function too. This process of drilling down to deeper and deeper levels produces a fuller, more-thorough picture of the whole. This is reductionism.
Life. That is what we are interested in. There are different organizational levels of life. Obviously, there is the level of the organism. For centuries, the only organisms known were plants and animals, and the organismal level was as far as biology had delved. Let’s stick with animals, since much of our knowledge of life was originally derived from them. How does an animal work? No one knew for sure. Animals jumped, ate, mated, slept, and died but detailed explanations of how these actions occurred were not known. As time went by, biology dug deeper and found that animals are composed of organ systems, which are themselves composed of organs. Then more detailed explanations could be provided (for example, the path that food took through the body and the fact that blood circulated instead of irrigating the body and then new blood being produced to replace that which was pumped out of the heart). But even this level did not suffice. Further research dug deeper into the tissue and cellular levels of organization. More detailed explanations were available. Indeed, each deeper level that was examined led to a greater understanding of how life operates. And within the last 100 or so years, the innards of the cell have been being investigated, leading to an even more complete understanding of life.
So to understand most fully how life works, and in order to provide the most detailed and convincing explanations for life-related phenomena, we have to dig down to the deepest levels of biological systems: biochemistry (gross anatomy is at far too high of a level).
quote:
With the advent of modern biochemistry we are now able to look at the rock-bottom level of life. (Michael J. Behe, Darwin’s Black Box: The Biochemical Challenge to Evolution, Free Press, 1996, p15)
quote:
When Leeuwenhoek used a microscope to see a tinier mite on a tiny flea, it inspired Jonathan Swift to write a ditty anticipating an endless procession of smaller and smaller bugs:
!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!
So naturalists observe, a flea
Has smaller fleas that on him prey;
And these have smaller still to bite ‘em;
And so proceed ad infinitum.
!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!
Swift was wrong; the procession does not go on forever. In the late twentieth century we are in the flood tide of research on life, and the end is in sight. The last remaining black box was the cell, which was opened to reveal molecules — the bedrock of nature. Lower we cannot go. Moreover, the work that has already been done on enzymes, other proteins, and nucleic acids has illuminated the principles at work at the ground level of life. Many details remain to be filled in, and some surprises undoubtedly remain. But unlike earlier scientists, who looked at a fish or a heart or a cell and wondered what it was and what made it work, modern scientists are satisfied that the actions of proteins and other molecules are sufficient explanations for the basis of life. From Aristotle to modern biochemistry, one layer after another has been peeled away until the cell — Darwin’s black box — stands open. (Michael J. Behe, Darwin’s Black Box: The Biochemical Challenge to Evolution, Free Press, 1996, p13)
quote:
In short, Dawkins’s explanation is only addressed to the level of what is called gross anatomy.
Both Hitching and Dawkins have misdirected their focus. The eye, or indeed almost any large biological structure, consists of a number of discrete systems. The function of the retina alone is the perception of light. The function of the lens is to gather light and focus it. If a lens is used with a retina, the working of the retina is improved, but both retina and lens can work by themselves. Similarly, the muscles that focus the lens or turn the eye function as a contraction apparatus, which can be applied to many different systems. The perception of light by the retina is not dependent upon them. Tear ducts and eyelids are also complex systems, but separable from the function of the retina.
Hitching’s argument is vulnerable because he mistakes an integrated system of systems for a single system, and Dawkins rightly points out the separability of the components. Dawkins, however, merely adds complex systems to complex systems and calls that an explanation. This can be compared to answering the question How is a stereo system made? with the words By plugging a set of speakers into an amplifier, and adding a CD player, radio receiver, and tape deck. (Michael J. Behe, Darwin’s Black Box: The Biochemical Challenge to Evolution, Free Press, 1996, p38-39)
quote:
Biochemistry has demonstrated that any biological apparatus involving more than one cell (such as an organ or a tissue) is necessarily an intricate web of many different, identifiable systems of horrendous complexity. The simplest self-sufficient, replicating cell has the capacity to produce thousands of different proteins and other molecules, at different times and under variable conditions. Synthesis, degradation, energy generation, replication, maintenance of cell architecture, mobility, regulation, repair, communication — all of these functions take place is virtually every cell, and each function itself requires the interaction of numerous parts. Because each cell is such an interwoven meshwork of systems, we would be repeating the mistake of Francis Hitching by asking if multicellular structures could have evolved in step-by-step Darwinian fashion. (Michael J. Behe, Darwin’s Black Box: The Biochemical Challenge to Evolution, Free Press, 1996, p46)
quote:
The relevant steps in biological processes occur ultimately at the molecular level, so a satisfactory explanation of a biological phenomenon — such as sight, digestion, or immunity — must include its molecular explanation.
Now that the black box of vision has been opened, it is no longer enough for an evolutionary explanation of that power to consider only the anatomical structures of whole eyes, as Darwin did in the nineteenth century (and as popularizers of evolution continue to do today). Each of the anatomical steps and structures that Darwin thought were so simple actually involves staggeringly complicated biochemical processes that cannot be papered over with rhetoric. ...
Thus biochemistry offers a Lilliputian challenge to Darwin. Anatomy is, quite simply, irrelevant to the question of whether evolution could take place on the molecular level. So is the fossil record. It no longer matters whether there are huge gaps in the fossil record or whether the record is as continuous as that of U.S. presidents. And if there are gaps, it does not matter whether they can be explained plausibly. The fossil record has nothing to tell us about whether the interactions of 11-cis-retinal with rhodopsin, transducin, and phosphodiesterase could have developed step-by-step. ... Until recently ... evolutionary biologists could be unconcerned with the molecular details of life because so little was known about them. Now the black box of the cell has been opened, and the infinitesimal world that stands revealed must be explained. (Michael J. Behe, Darwin’s Black Box: The Biochemical Challenge to Evolution, Free Press, 1996, p22)

This message is a reply to:
 Message 115 by Loudmouth, posted 03-10-2004 11:07 AM Loudmouth has replied

Replies to this message:
 Message 121 by Loudmouth, posted 03-10-2004 3:17 PM DNAunion has replied

  
DNAunion
Inactive Member


Message 120 of 223 (91589)
03-10-2004 1:45 PM
Reply to: Message 115 by Loudmouth
03-10-2004 11:07 AM


quote:
loudmouth: And one more question for DNAUnion, and I would really like an answer in order to make this debate move along. Why does Behe exclude macroscopic/skeletal IC systems?
Besides the quotes I gave above, Behe also says this about the panda’s thumb:
quote:
Even then, why is Gould’s panda scenario incompatible with intelligent-design theory? The panda’s thumb is a black box. It is entirely possible that in the production of the Panda’s thumb, no new irreducibly complex systems were required in the cell. It is possible that the systems that were already present — the systems that make muscle proteins and nerve fibers, that lay down bone and matrix protein, that cause cells to divide for a while and then cease division — were enough. It is possible that these systems were quite sufficient to cause a bone protuberance when some chance event perturbed their normal pattern of operation, and it is possible that natural selection then favored this change. Design theory has nothing to say about a biochemical or biological system unless all of the components of the system are known and it is determined that the system is composed of several interacting parts. Intelligent-design theory can coexist quite peacefully with the panda’s thumb. (Michael Behe, Darwin’s Black Box: The Biochemical Challenge to Evolution, Free Press, 1996, p229)

This message is a reply to:
 Message 115 by Loudmouth, posted 03-10-2004 11:07 AM Loudmouth has not replied

  
DNAunion
Inactive Member


Message 122 of 223 (91651)
03-10-2004 7:04 PM
Reply to: Message 121 by Loudmouth
03-10-2004 3:17 PM


So are we all in agreement yet that the ossicles don't refute Behe because they don't form an IC system?

This message is a reply to:
 Message 121 by Loudmouth, posted 03-10-2004 3:17 PM Loudmouth has replied

Replies to this message:
 Message 123 by NosyNed, posted 03-10-2004 7:35 PM DNAunion has replied
 Message 130 by Loudmouth, posted 03-11-2004 2:01 PM DNAunion has not replied

  
DNAunion
Inactive Member


Message 124 of 223 (91657)
03-10-2004 7:48 PM
Reply to: Message 123 by NosyNed
03-10-2004 7:35 PM


quote:
I understand that many, if not all of Behe's original BIC systems have been shown to be evolvable. Is that true?
That's what I was getting at when I first started in this thread (either my first or second post). Why would someone rely on ossicles - which don't even meet Behe's usage of IC - when some of his actual examples have supposedly been refuted?

This message is a reply to:
 Message 123 by NosyNed, posted 03-10-2004 7:35 PM NosyNed has not replied

Replies to this message:
 Message 125 by Warren, posted 03-10-2004 10:09 PM DNAunion has not replied

  
DNAunion
Inactive Member


Message 126 of 223 (91680)
03-10-2004 11:01 PM
Reply to: Message 123 by NosyNed
03-10-2004 7:35 PM


quote:
NosyNed: Not if we use the original, simple sounding definition of Behe's.
I already pointed out that there is more to IC than a one-sentence definition.
Same goes for other things dealing with science, such as evolution. One of the most-used definitions of evolution is "changes in allelic frequencies in a population". If we stick to just that definition then we can't legitimately state that dinosaurs or trilobites evolved because we don't have access to their alleles.
[This message has been edited by DNAunion, 03-10-2004]

This message is a reply to:
 Message 123 by NosyNed, posted 03-10-2004 7:35 PM NosyNed has replied

Replies to this message:
 Message 127 by NosyNed, posted 03-11-2004 12:53 AM DNAunion has replied

  
DNAunion
Inactive Member


Message 128 of 223 (91722)
03-11-2004 8:27 AM
Reply to: Message 127 by NosyNed
03-11-2004 12:53 AM


quote:
DNAunion: I already pointed out that there is more to IC than a one-sentence definition.
Same goes for other things dealing with science, such as evolution. One of the most-used definitions of evolution is "changes in allelic frequencies in a population". If we stick to just that definition then we can't legitimately state that dinosaurs or trilobites evolved because we don't have access to their alleles.
quote:
NosyNed: I'd be tempted to argue that we do have access to the alleles since they show up in the phenotypes.
But then you’d be bringing in a new concept; one that is not part of the one-sentence definition of evolution. How is that materially different from bringing in the concept of minimal function into Behe’s usage of IC, which he mentions several times in his book?
Also, it is possible for a phenotype to change without there being an associated change in allelic frequencies. This can happen if the number of each allele in the population remains constant but their distribution — between heterozygotes and homozygotes — changes.
PS: I am not arguing against evolution, just making a point about the inadequacy of many one-sentence definitions.
quote:
NosyNed: However, I agree that things can be oversimplified. But I don't see more in Behe's definition of IC (other than restricting it to biochemical systems). Is there more to it?
Yes. Here is something I wrote up several years ago, back when I was an IDist (if one must pigeonhole). Even it is not complete (minimal function is not mentioned, nor are other things).
PS: I should point out that I am posting this as is, without updating it.
3) IRREDUCIBLE COMPLEXITY
Irreducible complexity is best defined by Dr. Michael Behe, who coined the term in his 1996 book Darwin’s Black Box: The Biochemical Challenge to Evolution. On page 39 of that book, he states:
quote:
By irreducibly complex I mean a single system composed of several well-matched, interacting parts that contribute to the basic function, wherein the removal of any one of the parts causes the system to effectively cease functioning.
So any system that has all 6 of the following attributes is IC:
(1) SINGLE SYSTEM
The system must be a single system. It cannot be a composite system, such as an automobile. Even though the reciprocating, four-stroke, internal-combustion engine of a car is probably IC, the car itself is not because its sound system and its air conditioning system can be removed without the car losing its function. These systems that could be removed without the car losing function are subsystems of the car (which means that a car is not a single system, but is rather an aggregate system composed of multiple systems). Not even the eye — which many people would simply assume counts as a single system — meets this criterion, as Behe points out.
quote:
Both Hitching and Dawkins have misdirected their focus. The eye, or indeed almost any large biological structure, consists of a number of discrete systems. The function of the retina alone is the perception of light. The function of the lens is to gather light and focus it. Tear ducts and eyelids are also complex systems, but separable from the function of the retina.
Hitching’s argument is vulnerable because he mistakes an integrated system of systems for a single system, and Dawkins rightly points out the separability of the components. (Michael Behe, Darwin’s Black Box: The Biochemical Challenge to Evolution, Free Press, 1996, p38)
(2) SEVERAL PARTS
The single system mentioned in (1) must be composed of several (i.e., at the absolute minimum, three) parts. A two-part system that requires each part - such as a natural lever system formed by one pine tree falling perpendicular to and on top of an already fallen pine tree - is not an IC system (note that such a fallen-tree-lever system also fails the criterion of parts having to be well matched, which will be discussed next). Everything else being equal, the greater the number of (interacting) parts in a system, the greater the system’s complexity; and the underlying concept of Behe’s book and argument is irreducible complexity, not irreducible simplicity.
(3) WELL-MATCHED PARTS
The several parts mentioned in (2) must be well matched. That is, the parts should physically fit together (and work together) so well that a change in one part’s size and/or shape would require compensatory changes in at least one other part’s size and/or shape. In addition, a well-matched part must be a solid, not a fluid.
For example, for a standard mouse trap (the object Behe uses to explain his concept of irreducible complexity), decreasing the length of the holding bar by half would necessitate an equivalent reduction in the size of the hammer as well as a large-scale adjustment in the position of the catch and probably the spring also. Similarly, doubling the length of the hammer would also necessitate concomitant changes in other parts: the holding bar’s length would need to be doubled, and its girth may need to be increased in order to handle the additional load, the catch would need to be repositioned, the length of the base would need to be increased, and a repositioning of the spring may be required. For an IC system, the parts’ sizes and shapes should be somehow specific to each other: generic parts are not well matched to each other.
quote:
The appearance of the modifier "well-matched" in the definition I constructed reflects the fact that complexity is a quantitative property. A system can be more or less complex, so the likelihood of coming up with any particular interactive system by chance can be more or less probable. As an illustration, contrast the greater complexity of a mechanical mousetrap with the much lesser complexity of a lever and fulcrum. Together a lever and fulcrum form an interactive system which can be used to move weights. Nonetheless, the parts of the system can have a wide variety of shapes and sizes and still function. Because the system is not well-matched, it could easily be formed by chance.
Systems requiring several parts to function that need not be well-matched, we can call "simple interactive" systems (designated 'SI'). Ones that require well-matched components are irreducibly complex ('IC').
let me first illustrate a well-matched system using the blood-clotting cascade (Stubbs and Bode 1994). The active form of one protein of the cascade is called thrombin, which cleaves the soluble protein fibrinogen to produce fibrin, the insoluble meshwork of a blood clot. The chemistry catalyzed by thrombin is simply the hydrolysis of a certain fibrinogen peptide bond. However, all proteins are made of amino acid residues joined by peptide bonds. A typical protein contains several hundred peptide bonds. There is nothing remarkable about the bond in fibrinogen that is cleaved by thrombin. Yet thrombin selects that particular bond for cleavage out of literally hundreds of thousands of peptide bonds in its environment and ignores almost all others. It can do this because the shape of thrombin is well-matched to the shape of fibrinogen around the bond it cleaves. It "recognizes" not only the bond it cuts, but also a number of other features of its target. The other proteins of the clotting cascade (Stuart factor, proaccelerin, tissue factor, and so on) have similar powers of discrimination. So do virtually all of the components of the molecular machines I discussed in Darwin's Black Box. (http://www.discovery.org/viewDB/index.php3?program=CRSC%2... )
So what does well-matched mean? I’ll give it a shot.
3a. Strong sense
match = to fit together (related to proper size and shape)
well = (1) to a high degree, and/or (2) to a large extent or degree, and/or (3) to an extent approaching completeness, and/or (4) without doubt or question
Well-matched: Physically fitting together both precisely and specifically due to having exactly the correct sizes and shapes (tailor made). A change in the size and/or shape of (at least the interacting portion of) one part would necessitate a compensatory modification to the size and/or shape of (at least the interacting portion of) the other part.
Example: An enzyme possessing great specificity for its substrate (due to their complementary, three-dimensional, recognition surfaces), or the moving, interlocking gears of either a transmission or a mechanical clock (they mesh together perfectly).
3b.Weaker sense
match = to fit together (related to proper size and shape)
well = (1) in a good or proper manner, or (2) satisfactorily with respect to conduct or action
Well-matched: Physically fitting together properly - that is, satisfactorily enough to perform a particular action — due to having appropriate sizes and shapes. Though the two parts may not interlock or have large areas of complementary surface contact as they do in the strong sense, the size and shape of (at least some region of) each part are still constrained to being within certain fairly narrow parameters. If the size and/or shape of one part were changed by more than a trivial amount, a compensatory change in the size and/or shape of the other part would be required.
Example: The holding bar on a mechanical mouse trap that restrains the hammer from moving.
So what does well-matched not mean?
Argument: If a system is able to function, then its parts must be well matched.
Counter: A functioning lever system made of non-well-matched parts can be produced by numerous different-sized and/or different-shaped objects (diving board, refrigerator, bookshelf, tree branch, car, etc.) coming to lie perpendicularly across a fallen pine tree.
Argument: If a system is able to function well, then its parts must be well matched
Counter: A functioning lever system consisting of non-well-matched parts (such as was just described) can perform its function well.
Argument: In a water-channel system, water is a well-matched part as it perfectly fits the specific three-dimensional contours of the other parts (the two sides and bottom)
Counter: Fluids do not fit Behe's usage of "well-matched". His usage of "well-matched" pertains to solid objects that physically fit together well due to their shapes and sizes. If a fluid (liquid or gas) is poured into a cylindrical container, it will immediately conform to that particular shape (becoming cylindrical). If that very same fluid were then poured into a cubic container, it would immediately conform to that particular shape (becoming cubic). If that very same fluid were next poured into a container of irregular shape, it would immediately conform that that particular shape (becoming irregular). And if a liquid were poured out onto the floor, it would immediately conform to the floor's particular contour (becoming flat). A single fluid (liquid or gas) conforms to whatever shape it is contained in. As such, it cannot be considered a well-matched part according to Behe's usage. The reason? Lack of specificity: fluids are the ultimate conformers. In the following quote, Behe explains that the components of the BZ reaction are not well matched because those parts are generic and fit a wide range of other parts that are not components of the system under consideration.
quote:
BEHE: Let's contrast this biochemical specificity [of the specificity of the blood-clotting enzymes] with a comparable chemical reaction lacking such specificity. The peptide bonds of proteins can also be cleaved by simple chemicals. A typical procedure calls for incubating the protein in 6N hydrochloric acid at 110C for twenty four hours. If fibrinogen were incubated under those conditions, the peptide bond that thrombin leaves would be broken, but so would every other peptide bond in the protein. It would be completely reduced to amino acids. If thrombin were in the mix, it too would be completely destroyed. If the other proteins of the clotting cascade were there, no clotting would take place, even though the peptide bonds that are cleaved in the cascade would be cleaved, because all other peptide bonds would be hydrolyzed too. There is virtually no specificity to the chemical hydrolysis beyond the type of bond that is cleaved.
Similarly, the reactants of the BZ reaction are small organic or inorganic chemicals that show little specificity for each other. One ingredient, sodium bromate, is a general purpose oxidizing reagent and is capable of degrading a very large spectrum of chemicals besides the ones used in BZ reactions (thus its transport aboard airlines is forbidden). Another requirement of the reaction is simply for a transition metal that can change its oxidation state, and a number of such metals are known, including iron, cerium, and manganese ions (Field 1972). A third requirement is for an organic molecule that can be oxidized. Many candidates could fulfill this role (ones that have been used include malonic, citric, maleic, and malic acids), and organic molecules can be oxidized by many reagents other than bromate. The last ingredient is simply a high concentration of sulfuric acid. As Field (1972, 308) noted, setting up BZ reactions "is an exceedingly easy task as they will occur over a wide range of concentrations and conditions."
(http://www.discovery.org/viewDB/index.php3?program=CRSC%2...)
(4) INTERACTING PARTS
The several parts mentioned in (2) must interact. A system that is composed of non-interacting parts is not IC. This includes:
4a. A system in which the components are stationary/static. For example, the pieces of a standard jigsaw puzzle interlock, but they do not interact.
4b. A system in which the components are arranged in a simple serial manner, with each one acting upon the next in line (such as a line of falling dominoes). Here the distinction is between acting and interacting.
The problem with 4b is that the parts are merely acting on the next in line, as opposed to interacting with multiple other parts in various ways. It is clear that there is a distinction between:
4b-1: A system composed of a series of things in which each is merely acted upon by (and/or dependent upon) the next in line (such as a food chain, or an A->B->C->D metabolic pathway).
4b-2: A system composed of a group of things arranged into an interacting (and/or interdependent) network, with each of the parts acting/depending upon multiple others such that various linkages run from each part in multiple directions to form a complex meshwork of interacting (and/or interdependent) parts (such as a food web, or a mouse trap).
Interactions that are made by forces being applied through direct, physical contact are clearly interactions; in the strong sense of the word. Interactions that occur only logically, or indirectly through intermediaries, are not clearly interactions of the type Behe requires (they are interactions in the weak sense and would need to be examined individually).
(5) PARTS CONTRIBUTE TO OVERALL FUNCTION
Each of the several parts mentioned in (2) must contribute to the system’s overall function. An accessory part is a part of the general system that (1) is not required for the functioning of the core IC system or (2) performs a function that does not tie directly in with that of the core IC system. For example, a mechanical mouse trap could have a rubber pad added to its base in order to make the trap easier to grasp or to dampen the sound of the SLAP associated with the forceful impact of the hammer with the base. But the rubber pad would not contribute to the catching of mice and so would serve a function unrelated to the overall function of the device. Any such accessory part does not count as being a part of an IC core system and must be eliminated from the parts mentioned in (2).
(6) ALL PARTS REQUIRED
Removal of any one of the several parts mentioned in (2) causes the system to lose function. A system can have an IC core with accessory parts added on. Consider again a rubber pad added to the base of a mechanical mouse trap. We already saw that the pad is an accessory part because it serves a function unrelated to the overall system’s function. But even if that weren’t true, the rubber pad would still be a mere accessory part because it could be removed without leading to the loss of system function. In such a case, the accessory parts are part of the overall system, but they are not part of the *IC* core system, and must be eliminated from the parts mentioned in (2).
quote:
The reason for the conclusion [that a watch must be designed] is just as Paley implied: the ordering of separate components to accomplish a function beyond that of the individual components. The function of the watch is to act as a timekeeping device. Its components are the various gears, springs, chains, and the like that Paley lists.
So far, so good. But if Paley knows what to look for in his mechanical paradigm, why did he go downhill so quickly? Because he got carried away and started looking to the wrong features of the watch. The problems start when Paley digresses from systems of necessarily interacting components to talk about arrangements that simply fit his idea of the way things ought to be. The first hint of trouble comes in Paley’s opening paragraph, when he mentions that the watch’s wheels are made of brass to prevent rust. The problem is that the exact material, brass, is not required for the watch to function. It might help, but a watch can function with wheels made of almost any hard material — probably even wood or bone. Things only get worse when Paley mentions the glass cover of the watch. Not only is the exact material not required, but the whole component is dispensable: a cover is not necessary for the function of the watch. A watch cover is simply a convenience that has been attached to an irreducibly complex system, not a part of the system itself. (bold emphasis added, italic emphasis in the original, Michae lBehe, Darwin’s Black Box: The Biochemical Challenge to Evolution, Free Press, 1996, p 215-216)
Note that confusion often arises when people remove what they believe to be a part from a system Behe determined to be IC with the resulting system still being functional (which appears to refute Behe’s claims). The problem is usually that these people are not removing a part of the IC system, but rather are removing either an accessory part (see (5) and (6) just above) or a part of one of the parts of the IC system. For example, consider a system that typically has say 12 copies of a rod-like structure that together form some sort of a barrel that is one of the several parts of the IC system. Someone may find that 1, 2, or 3 copies of the rod-like structure that combine to form the barrel can be removed without the system losing function. They might then claim to have falsified an example of IC, but they would be wrong. The barrel — which was the part of the IC system - is still there, functioning as it was before: it itself just has fewer components now than before. So this would not be the removal of a part of the system, but rather the removal of a part of a part of the system (it would be merely a subpart of the system that was eliminated). The individual parts of an IC system do not have to be IC themselves: parts of a part of the IC system, or copies of a multi-component part, can be taken away from an IC system without the resulting system losing function, without contradicting Behe’s definition/example at all.

This message is a reply to:
 Message 127 by NosyNed, posted 03-11-2004 12:53 AM NosyNed has replied

Replies to this message:
 Message 129 by NosyNed, posted 03-11-2004 11:08 AM DNAunion has replied

  
DNAunion
Inactive Member


Message 132 of 223 (91821)
03-11-2004 6:51 PM
Reply to: Message 129 by NosyNed
03-11-2004 11:08 AM


quote:
NosyNed:
****************************
DNAunion: Note that confusion often arises when people remove what they believe to be a part from a system Behe determined to be IC with the resulting system still being functional (which appears to refute Behe’s claims). The problem is usually that these people are not removing a part of the IC system, but rather are removing either an accessory part (see (5) and (6) just above) or a part of one of the parts of the IC system.
****************************
but:
****************************
Behe: By irreducibly complex I mean a single system composed of several well-matched, interacting parts that contribute to the basic function, wherein the removal of any one of the parts causes the system to effectively cease functioning.
*****************************
These two quotes are contradictory. Note especially the emphasis in the first. If Behe determined it to be IC then no parts can be removed without it ceasing to function. But if a part can be removed it is shown to have been miscast as IC.
This is an apparent contradiction, not an actual one.
A good example of this is the cilium, which Behe states is IC. Kenneth Miller claimed to have refuted Behe by showing that some cilia are missing key parts, such as the central microtubule doublet and the outer dynein arms. Problem for Miller is that Behe doesn’t include them as being parts of the IC cilium: they’re accessory structures. The fact that neither the outer dynein arms nor the central doublet are required for ciliary motion is irrelevant to Behe’s claim of IC and can’t possibly be used to refute him.
The problem here is that people don’t try to understand what Behe actually means. If a person reads Behe’s book and tries to understand his argument, they will understand that when Behe says the cilium (or some other system) is IC he means that the cilium contains an IC core. The IC core consists of a subset of the parts of the whole system wherein each element of the subset is required for system function. Accessory parts can be tacked onto such a core. Those other parts, not required for system function, would be parts of the system as a whole but not part of the (core) IC system.

This message is a reply to:
 Message 129 by NosyNed, posted 03-11-2004 11:08 AM NosyNed has replied

Replies to this message:
 Message 135 by NosyNed, posted 03-11-2004 8:13 PM DNAunion has replied

  
DNAunion
Inactive Member


Message 133 of 223 (91824)
03-11-2004 7:03 PM
Reply to: Message 129 by NosyNed
03-11-2004 11:08 AM


quote:
NosyNed: An earlier discussion of yours had Behe moving down to strictly biochemical systems. Why then does he use a mousetrap as an aid to understanding when it is, by definition, outside of what he is considering.
He uses a mousetrap for several reasons. First, because most everyday Joes, who know nothing about eukaryotic cilia, are familiar with a mousetrap. Therefore, he can explain the general concepts in the first few chapters and not overwhelm the reader with too many details all at once. Second, he — and anyone else - can pick up a mousetrap, identify the various parts, move them, and see how they interact: that’s not possible with a cilium. Finally, despite what some earlier statements may have led one to believe, a mousetrap is not outside of his definition of an IC system. If you will note, I qualified my statements by saying that Behe rejects macroscopic BIOLOGICAL systems from being IC: macroscopic mechanical systems can be IC if they meet the certain criteria. The key difference is that a macroscopic biological system — such as an organ or organ system — is never a single system: it’s always an integrated system of a multitude of separate systems. On the other hand, a mousetrap is indeed a single system: it’s parts (hammer, spring, holding bar, etc.) are the lowest level one needs to drill down to in order to give a fully satisfactory and detailed explanation for the system’s function.
[This message has been edited by DNAunion, 03-11-2004]

This message is a reply to:
 Message 129 by NosyNed, posted 03-11-2004 11:08 AM NosyNed has replied

Replies to this message:
 Message 134 by NosyNed, posted 03-11-2004 8:10 PM DNAunion has replied

  
DNAunion
Inactive Member


Message 136 of 223 (91862)
03-11-2004 8:31 PM
Reply to: Message 134 by NosyNed
03-11-2004 8:10 PM


quote:
NosyNed: I can not understand a mousetrap without drilling down to a lower level than the parts mentioned. If I thought I could I would be mistified when a mousetrap with inadequate friction between some of the parts would fail to 'set' correctly.
Friction isn’t a part. The lowest level parts needed for a full explanation of a mechanical mousetrap are the hammer, spring, platform, etc.
quote:
NosyNed: If we do take a mousetrap as being IC then, of course, it has been shown that a conventional mousetrap can operate without all the parts. This doesn't mean that taking one part of an existing mousetrap leaves it working. It is just that a mousetrap can exist and work with out all the current parts but with different arrangements and forms of the parts left.
Details?
quote:
NosyNed: It does appear that it is difficult or impossible to even determine what is actually IC. The definition seems to be about as sharp as the edge of a cloud.
Many things related to science have fuzzy borders: Are viruses living? Is Pluto a planet? These things existing in a gray area doesn’t mean that the concepts of living and planets are invalid. Some things are clearly living, some are clearly not; some things are clearly plantes, some are clearly not.
[This message has been edited by DNAunion, 03-11-2004]

This message is a reply to:
 Message 134 by NosyNed, posted 03-11-2004 8:10 PM NosyNed has replied

Replies to this message:
 Message 137 by NosyNed, posted 03-11-2004 8:49 PM DNAunion has replied

  
Newer Topic | Older Topic
Jump to:


Copyright 2001-2023 by EvC Forum, All Rights Reserved

™ Version 4.2
Innovative software from Qwixotic © 2024